Formula of the day: CCCpqrCsCCqCrtCqt
The last two formulas of the day were CpCqp and CCpCqrCCpqCpr. Together these form a set of axioms sufficient for the positive implicational calculus (equivalently they form a "basis" for the positive implicational calculus). C. A. Meredith figured out that CCCpqrCsCCqCrtCqt itself serves as a basis for the positive implicational calculus of propositions. To prove that{CpCqp-RVP, CCpCqrCCpqCpr-SD} yields CCCpqrCsCCqCrtCqt we can construct a demonstration as follows, with Ci standing for conditional introduction:
hypothesis 1 ! CCpqr
hypothesis 2 !@ s
hypothesis 3 !@# CqCrt
hypothesis 4 !@#$ q
RVP 5 !@#$ CqCpq
D5.4 6 !@#$ Cpq
D1.6 7 !@#$ r
D3.4 8 !@#$ Crt
D8.7 9 !@#$ t
Ci 4-9 10 !@# Cqt
Ci 3-10 11 !@ CCqCrtCqt
Ci 2-11 12 ! CsCCqCrtCqt
Ci 1-12 13 CCCpqrCsCCqCrtCqt.
We can expand all of this out and write a formal proof of {CCCpqrCsCCqCrtCqt} from the basis {CpCqp-RVP, CCpCqrCCpqCpr-SD} using any decent proof of the deduction metatheorem. Here the letters a, b, ..., n, o can get substituted by something else, but p, q, ..., y, z cannot. First we'll take out the "$" lines.
hypothesis 1 ! CCpqr
hypothesis 2 !@ s
hypothesis 3 !@# CqCrt
D[RVP].1 4 !@# CaCCpqr This is C4-1
D[SD].4 5 !@# CCaCpqCar
D5.RVP 6 !@# Cqr ... C4-7
D[RVP].3 7 !@# CaCqCrt ... C4-3
D[SD].7 8 !@# CCaqCaCrt
D8.[Caa] 9 !@# CqCrt ... C4-8
D[SD].9 10 !@# CCqrCqt
D10.6 11 !@# Cqt C4-9
.
.
.
Now for the "#" lines in the above demonstration. C3-3 and C3-9 match exactly. C3-10 we can obtain simply from SD just by substitution.
hypothesis 1 ! CCpqr
hypothesis 2 !@ s
theorem 3 !@ CCaCbCcdCaCCbcCbd (we'll use this when we used "SD" above)
D[RVP].1 4 !@ CaCCpqr
D[RVP].4 5 !@ CaCbCCpqr ... C3-4
D3.5 6 !@ CaCCbCpqCbr ... C3-5
theorem 7 !@ CaCbCcb
D[SD].6 8 !@ CCaCbCpqCaCbr
D8.7 9 !@ CaCqr ... C3-6
D3.RVP 10 !@ CCabCCcaCcb ... C3-8
D[SD].SD 11 !@ CCCaCbcCabCCaCbcCac
D11.9 12 !@ CCqCraCqa C3-11
Now the "@" lines.
hypothesis 1 ! CCpqr
theorem 2 ! CCaCbCcdCaCCbcCbd
theorem 3 ! CCaCbCcCdeCaCbCCcdCce (we'll use this where we used 3 above)
D[RVP].1 4 ! CaCCpqr C2-1
D[RVP].4 5 ! CaCbCCpqr C2-4
D[RVP].5 6 ! CaCbCcCCpqr ... C2-5
D3.6 7 ! CaCbCCcCpqCcr ... C2-6
theorem 8 ! CaCbCcCdc ... C2-7
D2.7 9 ! CaCCbCcCpqCbCcr ... C2-8
D[SD].9 10 ! CCaCbCcCpqCaCbCcr
D10.8 11 ! CaCbCqr ... C2-9
theorem 12 ! CaCbCcb
D3.12 13 ! CaCCbcCCdbCdc ... C2-10
D[SD].SD 14 ! CCCaCbcCabCCaCbcCac
D[RVP].14 15 ! CaCCCbCcdCbcCCbCcdCbd ... C2-11
D[SD].15 16 ! CCaCCbCcdCbcCaCCbCcdCbd
D16.11 17 ! CaCCqCrbCqr ... C2-12
And now we'll write the formal proof (allowing substitution for all lower case letters):
axiom 1 CpCqp C1-4
axiom 2 CCpCqrCCpqCpr
D1.2 3 CpCCqCrsCCqrCqs
D2.3 4 CCpCqCrsCpCCqrCqs ... SD above
D1.4 5 CpCCqCrCstCqCCrsCrt
D2.5 6 CCpCqCrCstCpCqCCrsCrt 2 above
D1.6 7 CpCCqCrCsCtuCqCrCCstCsu
D2.7 8 CCpCqCrCsCtuCpCqCrCCstCsu ... 3 above
D1.1 9 CpCqCrq
D2.9 10 CCpqCpCrq
D10.1 11 CpCqCrp ... C1-5
D10.11 12 CpCqCrCsp ... C1-6
D1.9 13 CpCqCrCsr ... C1-12
D1.13 14 CpCqCrCsCts ... C1-8
D8.12 15 CCpqCrCsCCtpCtq ... C1-7
D6.15 16 CCpqCrCCsCtpCsCtq ... C1-9
D4.16 17 CCpqCCrCsCtpCrCsCtq ... C1-10
D2.17 18 CCCpqCrCsCtpCCpqCrCsCtq
D18.14 19 CCCpqrCsCtCqr ... C1-11
D8.13 20 CpCqCCrsCCtrCts ... C1-13
D4.3 21 CpCCCqCrsCqrCCqCrsCqs ... C1-14
D1.21 22 CpCqCCCrCstCrsCCrCstCrt ... C1-15
D4.22 23 CpCCqCCrCstCrsCqCCrCstCrt ... C1-16
D2.23 24 CCpCqCCrCstCrsCpCqCCrCstCrt
D24.19 25 CCCpqrCsCCqCrtCqt
I'll point out that CCpqCCrpCrq is a theorem of this system as follows:
axiom 1 CpCqp
axiom 2 CCpCqrCCpqCpr
D1.2 3 CpCCqCrsCCqrCqs
D2.3 4 CCpCqCrsCpCCqrCqs
D4.1 5 CCpqCCrpCrq
But, even though it did appear in the set-ups to prove CCCpqrCsCCqCrtCqt, we never produced an actual proof of CCpqCCrpCrq, though we did produce a proof of CpCqCCrsCCtrCts in which CCpqCrpCrq can get said to qualify as contained within. I've used Prover9 to find a proof of {CpCqp, CCpCqrCCpqCpr} from {CCCpqrCsCCqCrtCqt}. Meredith also found that CtCCpqCCCspCqrCpr can also serve as a basis of the positive implicational calculus. Ted Ulrich has found some other single axioms for this system here.
Both axioms, "CtCCpqCCCspCqrCpr" and "CCCpqrCsCCqCrtCqt" have 17 symbols. A stronger system, the implicational calculus of propositions, has a single axiom with just 13 symbols.
Also, the conversion procedure I used implicitly here depends on *how* a particular meta-proof of the deduction meta-theorem works. If we have a different meta-proof of the deduction meta-theorem, we'll have a different conversion procedure. My May 10th answer here shows the same process via a distinct meta-proof of the meta-deduction theorem.
Wednesday, May 7, 2014
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment